Christmas Spirit In The Brain: Neural Imaging Finds Brain Network. The End of God’s Existence?

Difficulty Level: A-Level

In 2015, a team of scientists in Copenhagen decided to see if they could find the parts of the brain responsible for the Christmas Spirit. They gathered ten individuals who had Christmas traditions and ten individuals who did not. Pictures related and unrelated to Christmas were shown while they underwent BOLD imaging (Blood Oxygen Level Dependent). By comparing the two groups, the scientists were able to discover that certain areas of the brain were activated more in individuals who had Christmas traditions than those which who did not. It was concluded that these areas of the brain were responsible for the Christmas spirit.

Such findings are not restricted to Christmas Spirit. Other brain networks have been discovered to be responsible for faith based activities. Such evidence has been used to suggest that a God does not exist. Any feeling of spirituality is the result of the brain, not a God. It is a psychological need. Not divine intervention. Thus, we do not need a God to exist.

Such arguments are not conclusive. There are still some options for the religious believer to use as a defense against such conclusions. For instance, they could assert that brain networks and the intervention of a divine God are two explanations that aren’t contradictory. God may have created our brains to have the capacity to be able to partake in the Christmas Spirit. Religious believers may also argue that of course God interacts with us through our brain. If our brain is a key part in how we perceive the physical world, then it would make sense for God to convey the Christmas spirit through it. Thus, they would argue atheists cannot use such scientific evidence to conclude that God does not exist.

However, this may not be a satisfying defense. The atheist may argue that this compromises the God that religious believers want to believe in. By God working through the brain, it seems to minimize God’s causal power that the religious believer initially assumes. If God designed the brain to have Christmas Spirit and leaves the brain, then God not be the interventionist that most religious believers want him to be. God may not be actively acting within the world but using it like a computer. This may be a compromise that the religious believer may not want to concede.

One-Time
Monthly
Yearly

Help us keep our blog content free!

Make a monthly donation

Make a yearly donation

Choose an amount

$5.00
$15.00
$100.00
$5.00
$15.00
$100.00
$5.00
$15.00
$100.00

Or enter a custom amount

$

Your contribution is appreciated.

Your contribution is appreciated.

Your contribution is appreciated.

DonateDonate monthlyDonate yearly

References

https://www.bmj.com/content/351/bmj.h6266.long

AQA A-Level Religious Studies Year 2 Text Book

A Priori, A Posteriori, A Fortiori: What Do They All Mean? Philosophy Basics

Difficulty level: Undergraduate/ Masters

A priori and a posteriori are common words within philosophy that are introduced to students on the A-Level specification. However, it wasn’t until I started my masters degree that I came across the term a fortiori. But what is the difference between them? And why are a priori and a posteriori paired together without a fortiori?

Contents

  1. Contents
  2. Introduction
  3. What does a priori mean?
  4. What does a posteriori mean? How does it relate to a priori?
  5. Is there any common ground between a fortiori and the previous definitions?

Introduction

A priori and a posteriori are common words within philosophy that are introduced to students on the A-Level specification. However, it wasn’t until I started my masters degree that I came across the term a fortiori. But what is the difference between them? And why are a priori and a posteriori paired together without a fortiori?

What does a priori mean?

A priori refers to something which is known without having to appeal to experience. If we were to lock ourselves into a cave and gained knowledge via purely thinking, this knowledge would be a priori. The justification for believing in such knowledge would be independent of experience. This can include:

A) Propositions
We can know 1+1=2 purely via thinking.

B) Arguments
Tautologies are the most common example. These are arguments which arise from definition. We can know that a bachelor is an unmarried man just by looking at a definition. Such arguments can include ontological arguments for the existence of God: if we define God as the perfect being and it is better to exist than not exist, then God must exist.

What does a posteriori mean? How does it relate to a priori?

A posteriori is the opposite to a priori. It refers to arguments or propositions where the justification involves appealing to experience.

A) Propositions
Ravens are black. You would not be able to know this if you hadn’t encountered some form of the concept of raven through interactions with the world.

B) Arguments
Design arguments are the most common (though not always – they can be a mixture of a priori and a posteriori premises.) Essentially, they look to features of the world and argue there are elements signify design. From this, they argue that there must be a designer, who is God. You would not be able to make such an argument without experiencing the world first and seeing the features of design. Thus, it is an a posteriori argument.

Is there any common ground between a fortiori and the previous definitions?

A fortiori refers to justification. However, it does not refer to experience. Instead, it signifies where we have stronger grounds for one argument or conclusion over another. It is similar to, ‘to an even greater extent.’ For instance, if you have a person who is 15 and deemed too young to drink alcohol, then, a fortiori, a person who is 13 is also deemed too young to drink alcohol. With the younger age, there is a greater extent to which that person is too young to drink.

A fortiori can also be used when we reject one conclusion in favor of another because we deem to have stronger justification. For instance, we may accept that God does not exist because, in our eyes, the argument from the problem of evil is a fortiori to any argument which provides alternative explanations as to why there is evil in the world.

One-Time
Monthly
Yearly

Help us keep our blog content free!

Make a monthly donation

Make a yearly donation

Choose an amount

$5.00
$15.00
$100.00
$5.00
$15.00
$100.00
$5.00
$15.00
$100.00

Or enter a custom amount

$

Your contribution is appreciated.

Your contribution is appreciated.

Your contribution is appreciated.

DonateDonate monthlyDonate yearly

Descartes Was Murdered… Or Was He? The Death Of Rene Descartes: Odd Histories

Rene Descartes is one of the most famous philosophers within the Western philosophical canon, contributing to many areas of philosophy such as metaphysics, philosophy of mind and philosophy of perception. However, his fame does not arise from his philosophical works alone. He also provides one of the most controversial deaths within the philosophy world. Not even Descartes could have predicted that, when he passed away in Stockholm in 1950 at the age of 53, that the theories around his death would mainly focus on murder…

Natural death was the official story.

Initially, when concerning the official story provided by the court, Descartes death looked to be down to natural causes. The physician to examine the body declared Descartes had died of pneumonia. It seemed a likely cause. Descartes had been treating the Ambassador to France for it one week before and it is argued that Descartes may not have been used to the Swedish winter. Even within his writings, Descartes commented on the cold Nordic weather and the fact he was struggling with it.

Pneumonia doesn’t explain skin pigmentation… but arsenic does.

However, there are some problems with this manner of death. The largest challenge to the pneumonia theory is founded in a letter written by Johann Van Wullen, who was the private doctor of the queen. Eike Pies found the letters as they were written to a relative of his. While he diagnosed Descartes with pneumonia, he noted some odd symptoms which did not align with the condition. This included increased skin pigmentation and blood in the urine, symptoms which are often associated with arsenic poisoning. The physician was also not allowed to examine the body properly, including bleeding the body. Thus, Pies concluded that Descartes had in fact been poisoned.

Poisoned to protect the queen.

After discovering this evidence in 1980, the prevailing theory was that Descartes was poisoned by an unknown Protestant vicar. Descartes was raised a Catholic. However, Stockholm had undergone a bloody battle to convert to Protestantism. With Descartes being in charge of the Queen’s education, it was feared that he would cause her to revert to Catholicism. Thus, he had to be gotten rid of and this was done through poisoning him.

Theodore Ebert took this in almost a contradictory direction. After reviewing the evidence available, Ebert argued that Descartes was poisoned by Jacques Viogue, a missionary in Stockholm. Viogue believed that Queen Christina was considering converting to Catholicism due to her Catholic tendencies. However, he saw Descartes as a barrier to this. While Descartes was raised a Catholic, Viogue saw his metaphysical picture as more Calvenist. Thus, he decided to poison Descartes in order to stop him influencing the queen not to convert.

Evidence of tumor… but was it Descartes’ skull?

One final argument of how Descartes died is provided by Phillipe Charlier. His conclusions derived from an examination of Descartes’ ‘skull,’ which resides at Paris’ National Museum of Natural History. While doing the examination, Charlier discovered evidence of a sinus tumor. This account is problematic on two accounts. Firstly, Descartes never reported symptoms of a sinus tumor within his writing. Secondly, no one knows exactly where Descartes skull is. There are multiple museums claiming they have Descartes’ skull as it was removed from the skeleton at an unknown point in history. Theories of where the skull is will be covered in a future blog post, but it is safe to say that analyzing a ‘skull’ said to be Descartes is not convincing evidence.

References

https://www.theguardian.com/world/2010/feb/14/rene-descartes-poisoned-catholic-priest

Descartes’ skull

https://www.newser.com/story/197052/hi-tech-scan-of-descartes-skull-reveals-secret.html

https://www.britannica.com/biography/Rene-Descartes/Final-years-and-heritage

https://litestraboen.blogspot.com/2007/04/why-did-descartes-die.html#:~:text=Five%20months%20after%20his%20arrival%2C%20the%2011th%20February,got%20also%20ill%20and%20died%20one%20week%20later.

Book Club: ‘At The Existentialist Cafe: Freedom, Being, And Apricot Cocktails’ By Sarah Bakewell Chapter Three *Spoilers*

If you would like to read, At the Existentialist Cafe: Freedom, Being And Apricot Cocktails along with us, you can buy a copy here.

The next chapter of the book is focused on Martin Heidegger. Born in Messkirch, Heidegger took a similar path to Husserl. He didn’t initially intend to study philosophy. However, while at university, he discovered his love for it. His initial obsession was with Franz Brentano’s doctoral thesis, but he soon began reading classics such as Aristotle. This influenced his ideas on phenomenology. After doing some unpaid work, Husserl got Heidegger a job, the seat that Husserl had retired from. Husserl saw Heidegger as the one who would inherit his work on phenomenology. Most likely, he used Heidegger as a crutch after losing his son in the war. Little did Husserl know that he would eventually be deeply disappointed and the city of Freiburg would become The City of the Two Phenomenologists.

Despite Husserl taking Heidegger under his wing, Heidegger had multiple problems with Husserl’s ideas around phenomenology. The most pressing was Husserl’s focus on removing an individual’s being from the rest of the world. This same ‘mistake’ is one that many philosophers have made over time, the most prominent example of Descartes and the Evil Demon. Heidegger argued that an object’s being cannot be separated from the world around it. If you do, you miss being entirely. Being is a network which arises from the fact that, most of the time, our own being is interacting with something rather than contemplating it. When we are interacting with a boat, we look at how useful it is to us, such as whether it can get us across the lake. Thus, Husserl misses the entire point of Being.

However, it should be noted that Heidegger did note that there are instances where this coexistence of beings fails. There are times when the boat can no longer carry us across the lake as it springs a leak half way through the journey. This failure means our being’s interactions with other beings breaks down and we directly contemplate the object at hand. This has a significant change on how our world works.

The other mistake that Husserl made in Heidegger’s eyes was to not distinguish between particular instances of being and Being (this is complicated, but bear with.) For Heidegger, Being cannot be defined. Everything within the world has being – a church, a mouse, a piece of grass, us as humans. We know all of these things must have some Being as we are experiencing them. However, if we were to ask what all of these things had in common in order to define what being is, then we would become stuck. We would be unable to describe what this essence was. Heidegger this argues that Being is not a property or a ‘kind’. It is indefinable. This has important philosophical implications, particularly when considered against Husserl’s mission to be able to define Being.

The philosophy within the chapter thus boils down to two starkly different philosophyies. On the one hand, you have Husserl with his isolated, idealist account, concerned only with how objects appear within our consciousness. On the other, you see Heidegger’s account that emphasizes an the interconnectedness of our beings with others’ and their use within their networks.

The small detail I appreciated with this chapter is the subheadings. In this chapter’s subheading, Heidegger is described as a magician who appears. While providing an overview of the chapter, it continues the beautiful descriptions of Bakewell and peaks the interest of the reader for the chapter. It’s a nice touch from Bakewell, who continues to keep the philosophy she is explaining alive. It is a mere reflection of the vividness and passion that she writes the entire chapter with. It ignites an enjoyment from anyone who reads the book.

The part which captured my imagination the most was the comment by Pitch, a student of Heidegger. He made the comment that Heidegger could be described as a stormy landscape with a tree being uprooted in the center. There is a darker side to being a philosopher. Philosophers are often at the edge of the worst moments within life. While it has eroded now a days, philosophers should be the first to be asked about the hardest parts of life, whether its life, death or suffering. These cannot solely be answered with science. This can take a toll or be a heavy weight to burden, particularly when philosophers get it wrong. I felt this weight on Heidegger shoulder’s through this quote.

How much I am enjoying this book is well documented throughout the previous chapters I have analysed. However, with this chapter, there a few things that could be improved. From a philosophical perspective, there could have been greater clarity with how the philosophy was explained. It should be noted that Heidegger is an incredibly difficult philosopher to explain, particularly with how specifically he used his terminology. From quickly skimming the next pages, I think this chapter is an impartial account and will be revisited in the next chapter. However, I still feel there is room to provide a better account.

A more subjective aspect that would have been nice to have seen is an introduction focusing on the relationship between Husserl and Heidegger. From the way she portrays it, the relationship was filled with it all; friendship, betrayal, bitterness, and drama. The heart break and the treachery in the chapter is tangible between Husserl, the father who loved, and the adopted son who wanted to carve out his own legacy. With the captivating writing style she has maintained, emphasizing this bitter battle would have been a fantastic way to start the chapter, rather than focusing on a quote from Plato.

A final, more technical point around this chapter is Bakewell’s comments on Heidegger’s use of language. While she does briefly acknowledge the philosophical importance of questions within language, she mostly sees it from a pedantic point of view, arising from Heidegger’s own ego wanting to change how philosophers saw the world of metaphysics. However, I have to mostly disagree with her on this point. Philosophy and how it is used is of vital importance within philosophy. On the surface, it may seem ridiculous. However, the use of specific words often not only carries what they are referring to, but also can portray a series of judgements and values behind them. For instance, an individual may be described as ‘fat’. On the one hand, this refers to a person of a particular size. However, it also denotes other ideas within our society. For instance, it may portray that someone shouldn’t be the size they are or that a person is lesser than others because of their size. It can hold a whole world of hurt for those who carry the shame of being ‘fat’ with them. Thus, from a philosophical point of view, it seems reasonable for Heidegger to introduce new terms in order to battle against the stereotypes that persevered within metaphysics. While I agree with Bakewell that there is some level of pedantry to this at points, she could have gone further with her acknowledgement of an important aspect of philosophy.

What do you think? Do you think Heidegger would have been proud at how we cut to the issue at hand? Or would he say we were ‘Heideggerizing’? Are there aspects that you would like the blog to explain? Let us know below?

If you would like to read, At the Existentialist Cafe: Freedom, Being And Apricot Cocktails along with us, you can buy a copy here.

The Importance of Bodily Autonomy: Nurse Gives Patients Saline Instead of Vaccine

On Thursday 12th August, BBC News reported that a nurse in Germany had been giving patients an injection of saline (a harmless mixture of water and salt) instead of the Covid vaccination. She defended herself by arguing that she only did it to six patients due to dropping a number of vials needed to give them the vaccine. However, she is under suspicion for doing the same to over 8000 patients. Hence, it is suspected that the motive was a political one: the nurse is accused of being an anti-vaxer. For some, the case may not appear too bad. Saline is a harmless solution. However, the immorality of the case cuts deeply into philosophical issues around bodily autonomy.

‘Bodily autonomy is an individuals’ ability to make decisions about actions that will impact their body from a complete foundation of knowledge.’

What is bodily autonomy? It is an individuals’ ability to make decisions about actions that will impact their body from a complete foundation of knowledge. It is an individual’s right to decide how their own body should be treated. For instance, when someone denies a surgery to remove a tumor from their body, the decision is respected as the decision due to the individuals’ bodily autonomy. If someone then proceeded to carry out the surgery, then that would defy their bodily autonomy and would be morally wrong.

Bodily autonomy has a significant baring on multiple questions within philosophy. It is most obvious within the Pro-Choice movement, which argues women should be allowed to choose whether they have an abortion. Part of this argument arises from bodily autonomy; women should be able to have control of their own bodies and decide what is the right thing for it. It also plays a part in the Philosophy of Sex around consent. Individuals must be able to decide what they do with their bodies and whether they have sex.

Some argue that violations of bodily autonomy are far stronger than any other moral crime that can be committed. The violation of bodily autonomy is a special kind of wrong that hits us differently. This is why things such as rape or grievous bodily harm tend to carry higher prison sentences. (However, this can be a debatable premise. Instances of mental or verbal bullying can carry more scars than any other kind of physical harm. )

‘The nurse decided to undermine this bodily autonomy.’

This is the crux of the immorality of the case above; the individuals who wanted to get the vaccine had reviewed the pros and cons around getting the vaccine. They had made an informed choice with the information they had been given about how their body should be treated. However, the nurse decided to undermine this bodily autonomy. She defied their decision and gave them saline instead. Thus, her action was deeply immoral.

Some individuals may argue that the breaking of bodily autonomy is overemphasized within this article. There are some instances where bodily autonomy should be undermined. Breaking it does not necessarily lead to immorality:

Imagine that the nurse is on her way to the vaccination room when she overhears a conversation among the doctors. They comment that the injection isn’t a vaccine at all, but poison that will kill a person over two years. The nurse then proceeds to the vaccination room where she gives the person saline instead of the vaccination.

Philosopher Ad Absurdum

In the case above, bodily autonomy would not matter. The individuals may have made the decision to receive the vaccination and exercised their right to bodily autonomy. However, the nurse still did the right thing in denying them the vaccine. Thus, for some, the breaking of bodily autonomy in the original case would not have significant moral sway.

There is no doubt that there will be some individuals that would go as far as to argue that the nurse did indeed do the right thing and there is no difference between the original case and the adapted case. However, there are clearly significant moral differences that should be accounted for between the two examples.

Firstly, there is the question of knowledge. In the adapted case, there was something that the nurse new but those who were being vaccinated didn’t; that the injection was a poison rather than a vaccine. In this instance, it would be denied that the individual had actually exercised bodily autonomy. For bodily autonomy to be present, a decision must be made based on accurate information and the capacity for reasoning must be present. If there was something the individual didn’t know, then the individual would not have bodily autonomy. Thus, in the adapted case the nurse would be doing the right thing because there is no breaking of bodily autonomy. However, in the original instance, it is unclear that the nurse had any piece of knowledge that the individuals being vaccinated did not have. The individuals were well informed and thus were in a position to make a decision for their body. Thus, the nurse broke the bodily autonomy of the individuals she refused to vaccinate and her action was still morally wrong.

‘Surely there would be some situations where there is full bodily autonomy but that autonomy should be broken?’

Some may challenge this argument. Surely there would be situations where there is full bodily autonomy but that autonomy should be broken? There must be some situations where an individual makes a fully informed decision but we would still be morally obliged to stop them from making that decision.

The rejection of this argument can be illustrated through the example of smoking.

One of your friends is a smoker while you are not. Both of you know the risks that come with smoking; lung cancer, emphysema, strokes. However, your friend still makes the choice to smoke.

Philosopher Ad Absurdum

Despite knowing this is the wrong decision to make, you wouldn’t do anything to stop your friend from smoking. The reason for this is because they would have exercised full bodily autonomy. They were in full possession of the facts and made the decision still to smoke. Thus, the consequences of them choosing to smoke has no bearing on the morality of the situation for you. You still have to respect their bodily autonomy.

Thus in the case of the nurse, it may be true that she thought that the individuals were making the wrong decision in getting vaccinated. However, it does not alter the fact that she should not have prevented them from getting the vaccine. If they were capable of making rational decisions and were in full possession of the facts, the nurse had no right to make a decision for them about their own bodies, even if it was a harmless saline solution.

~o~

If you are still unvaccinated, you can find your local vaccination center here.

%d bloggers like this: